In spite of its difficulty, the
task of discussing the relation of analytical psychology to poetry affords
me a welcome opportunity to define my views on the much debated question
of the relations between psychology and art in general. Although the two
things cannot be compared, the close connections which undoubtedly exist
between them call for investigation. These connections arise from the fact
that the practice of art is a psychological activity and, as such, can be
approached from a psychogical angle. Considered in this light, art, like
any other human activity deriving from psychic motives, is a proper subject
for psychology. This statement, however, involves a very definite limitation
of the psychological viewpoint when we come to apply it in practice. Only
that aspect of art which consists in the process of artistic creation can
be a subject for psychological study, but not that which constitutes its
essential nature. The question of what art is in itself can never be answered
by the psychologist, but must he approached from the side of aesthetics.
A similar distinction must be made in the realm
of religion. A psychological approach is permissible only in regard to the
emotions and symbols which constitute the phenomenology of religion, but
which do not touch upon its essential nature. If the essence of religion
and art could be explained, then both of them would become mere subdivisions
of psychology. This is not to say that such violations of their nature have
not been attempted. But those who are guilty of them obviously forget that
a similar fate might easily befall psychology, since its intrinsic value
and specific quality would be destroyed if it were regarded as a mere activity
of the brain, and were relegated along with the endocrine functions to a
subdivision of physiology. This too, as we know, has been attempted.
Art by its very nature is not science, and science by
its very nature is not art; both these spheres of the mind have something
in reserve that is peculiar to them and can be explained only in its own
terms. Hence when we speak of the relation of psychology to art, we shall
treat only of that aspect of art which can be submitted to psychological
scrutiny without violating its nature. Whatever the psychologist has to
say about art will be confined to the process of artistic creation and has
nothing to do with its innermost essence. He can no more explain this than
the intellect can describe or even understand the nature of feeling. Indeed,
art and science would not exist as separate entities at all if the fundamental
difference between them had not long since forced itself on the mind. The
fact that artistic, scientific, and religious propensities still slumber
peacefully together in the small child, or that with primitives the beginnings
of art, science, and religion coalesce in the undifferentiated chaos of
the magical mentality, or that no trace of "mind" can be found in the natural
instincts of animals - all this does nothing to prove the existence of a
unifying principle which alone would justify a reduction of the one to the
other. For if we go so far back into the history of the mind that the distinctions
between its various fields of activity become altogether invisible, we do
not reach an underlying principle of their unity, but merely an earlier,
undifferentiated state in which no separate activities yet exist. But the
elementary state is not an explanatory principle that would allow us to
draw conclusions as to the nature of later, more highly developed states,
even though they must necessarily derive from it. A scientific attitude
will always tend to overlook the peculiar nature of these more differentiated
states in favour of their causal derivation, and will endeavour to subordinate
them to a general but more elementary principle.
These theoretical reflections seem to me
very much in place today, when we so often find that works of art, and particularly
poetry, are interpreted precisely in this manner, by reducing them to more
elementary states. Though the material he works with and its individual
treatment can easily be traced back to the poet's personal relations with
his parents, this does not enable us to understand his poetry. The same
reduction can be made in all sorts of other fields, and not least in the
case of pathological disturbances. Neuroses and psychoses are likewise reducible
to infantile relations with the parents, and so are a mans good and bad
habits, his beliefs, peculiarities, passions, interests, and so forth. It
can hardly be supposed that all these very different things must have exactly
the same explanation, for otherwise we would be driven to the conclusion
that they actually are the same thing. If a work of art is explained in
the same way as a neurosis, then either the work of art is a neurosis or
a neurosis is a work of art. This explanation isall very well as a play
on words, but sound common sense rebels against putting a work of art on
the same level as a neurosis. An analyst might, in an extreme case, view
a neurosis as a work of art through the lens of his professional bias, but
it would never occur to an intelligent layman to mistake a pathological
phenomenon for art, in spite of the undeniable fact that a work of art arises
from much the same psychological conditions as a neurosis. This is only
natural, because certain of these conditions are present in every individual
and, owing to the relative constancy of the human environment, are constantly
the same, whether in the case of a nervous intellectual, a poet, or a normal
human being. All have had parents, all have a father- or a mother-complex,
all know about sex and therefore have certain common and typical human difficulties.
One poet may be influenced more by his relation to his father, another by
the tie to his mother, while a third shows unmistakable traces of sexual
repression in his poetry. Since all this can be said equally well not only
of every neurotic but of every normal human being, nothing specific is gained
for the judgment of a work of art. At most our knowledge of its psychological
antecedents will have been broadened and deepened.
The school of medical psychology inaugurated
by Freud has undoubtedly encouraged the literary historian to bring certain
peculiarities of a work of art into relation with the intimate, personal
life of the poet. But this is nothing new in principle, for it has long
been known that the scientific treatment of art will reveal the personal
threads that the artist, intentionally or unintentionally, has woven into
his work. The Freudian approach may, however, make possible a more exhaustive
demonstration of the influences that reach back into earliest childhood
and play their part in artistic creation. To this extent the psychoanalysis
of art differs in no essential from the subtle psychological nuances of
a penetrating literary analysis. The difference is at most question of degree,
though we may occasionally be surprised by indiscreet references to things
which a rather more delicate touch might have passed over if only for reasons
of tact. This lack of delicacy seems to be a professional peculiarity of
the medical psychologist, and the temptation to draw daring conclusions
easily leads to flagrant abuses. A slight whiff of scandal often lends spice
to a biography, but a little more becomes a nasty inquisitiveness - bad
taste masquerading as science. Our interest is insidiously deflected from
the work of art and gets lost in the labyrinth of psychic determinants,
the poet becomes a clinical case and, very likely, yet another addition
to the curiosa of psychopathia sexualis. But this means that the
psychoanalysis of art has turned aside from its proper objective and strayed
into a province that is as broad as mankind, that is not in the least specific
of the artist and has even less relevance to his art.
This kind of analysis brings the work of
art into the sphere of general human psychology - where many other things
besides art have their origin. To explain art in these terms is just as
great a platitude as the statement that "every artist is a narcissist."
Every man who pursues his own goal is a "narcissist" - though one wonders
how permissible it is to give such wide cur-rency to a term specifically
coined for the pathology of neurosis. The statement therefore amounts to
nothing; it merely elicits the faint surprise of a bon mot. Since
this kind of analysis is in no way concerned with the work of art itself,
but strives like a mole to bury itself in the dirt as speedily as possible,
it always ends up in the common earth that unites all mankind. Hence its
explanations have the same tedious monotony as the recitals which one daily
hears in the consulting-room.
The reductive method of Freud is a purely
medical one, and the treatment is directed at a pathological or otherwise
unsuitable formation which has taken the place of the normal functioning.
It must therefore be broken down, and the way cleared for healthy adaptation.
In this case, reduction to the common human foundation is altogether appropriate.
But when applied to a work of art it leads to the results I have described.
It strips the work of art of its shimmering robes and exposes the nakedness
and drabness of Homo sapiens, to which species the poet and artist
also belong. The golden gleam of artistic creation - the original object
of discussion - is extinguished as soon as we apply to it the same corrosive
method which we use in analysing the fantasies of hysteria. The results
are no doubt very interesting and may perhaps have the same kind of scientific
value as, for instance, a post-mortem examination of the brain of Nietzsche,
which might conceivably show us the particular atypical form of paralysis
from which he died. But what would this have to do with Zarathustra?
Whatever its subterranean background may have been, is it not a whole world
in itself, beyond the human, all-too-human imperfections, beyond the world
of migraine and cerebral atrophy?
I have spoken of Freud's reductive method
but have not stated in what that method consists. It is essentially a medical
technique for investigating morbid psychic phenomena, and it is solely concerned
with the ways and means of getting round or peering through the foreground
of consciousness in order to reach the psychic background, or the unconscious.
It is based on the assumption that the neurotic patient represses certain
psychic contents because they are morally incompatible with his conscious
values. It follows that the repressed contents must have correspondingly
negative traits - infantile-sexual, obscene, or even criminal - which make
them unacceptable to consciousness. Since no man is perfect, everyone must
possess such a background whether he admits it or not. Hence it can always
be exposed if only one uses the technique of interpretation worked out by
Freud.
In the short space of a lecture I cannot,
of course, enter into the details of the technique. A few hints must suffice.
The unconscious background does not remain inactive, but betrays itself
by its characteristic effects on the contents of consciousness. For example,
it produces fantasies of a peculiar nature, which can easily be interpreted
as sexual images. Or it produces characteristic disturbances of the conscious
processes, which again can be reduced to repressed contents. A very important
source for knowledge of the unconscious contents is provided by dreams,
since these are direct products of the activity of the unconscious. The
essential thing in Freud's reductive method is to collect all the clues
pointing to the unconscious background, and then, through the analysis and
interpretation of this material, to reconstruct the elementary instinctual
processes. Those conscious contents which give us a clue to the unconscious
background are incorrectly called symbols by Freud. They are not
true symbols, however, since according to his theory they have merely the
role of signs or symptoms of the subliminal processes. The
true symbol differs essentially from this, and should be understood as an
expression of an intuitive idea that cannot yet be formulated in any other
or better way. When Plato, for instance, puts the whole problem of the theory
of knowledge in his parable of the cave, or when Christ expresses the idea
of the Kingdom of Heaven in parables, these are genuine and true symbols,
that is, attempts to express something for which no verbal concept yet exists.
If we were to interpret Plato's metaphor in Freudian terms we would naturally
arrive at the uterus, and would have proved that even a mind like Plato's
was still struck on a primitive level of infantile sexuality. But we would
have completely overlooked what Plato actually created out of the primitive
determinants of his philosophical ideas; we would have missed the essential
point and merely discovered that he had infantile sexual fantasies like
any other mortal. Such a discovery could be of value only for a man who
regarded Plato as superhuman, and who can now state with satisfaction that
Plato too was an ordinary human being. But who would want to regard Plato
as a god? Surely only one who is dominated by infantile fantasies and therefore
possesses a neurotic mentality. For him the reduction to common human truths
is salutary on medical grounds, but this would have nothing whatever to
do with the meaning of Plato's parable.
I have purposely dwelt on the application of medical
psychoanalysis to works of art because I want to emphasize that the psychoanalytic
method is at the same time an essential part of the Freudian doctrine. Freud
himself by his rigid dogmatism has ensured that the method and the doctrine
- in themselves two very different things - are regarded by the public as
identical. Yet the method may be employed with beneficial results in medical
cases without at the same time exalting it into a doctrine. And against
this doctrine we are bound to raise vigorous objections. The assumptions
it rests on are quite arbitrary. For example, neuroses are by no means exclusively
caused by sexual repression, and the same holds true for psychoses. There
is no foundation for saying that dreams merely contain repressed wishes
whose moral incompatibility requires them to be disguised by a hypothetical
dream-censor. The Freudian technique of interpretation, so far as it remains
under the influence of its own one-sided and therefore erroneous hypotheses,
displays a quite obvious bias.
In order to do justice to a work of art, analytical psychology
must rid itself entirely of medical prejudice; for a work of art is not
a disease, and consequently requires a different approach from the medical
one. A doctor naturally has to seek out the causes of a disease in order
to pull it up by the roots, but just as naturally the psychologist must
adopt exactly the opposite attitude towards a work of art. Instead of investigating
its typically human determinants, he will inquire first of all into its
meaning, and will concern himself with its determinants only in so far as
they enable him to understand it more fully. Personal causes have as much
or as little to do with a work of art as the soil with the plant that springs
from it. We can certainly learn to understand some of the plant's peculiarities
by getting to know its habitat, and for the botanist this is an important
part of his equipment. But nobody will maintain that everything essential
has then been discovered about the plant itself. The personal orientation
which the doctor needs when confronted with the question of aetiology in
medicine is quite out of place in dealing with a work of art, just because
a work of art is not a human being, but is something supra-personal. It
is a thing and not a personality; hence it cannot be judged by personal
criteria. Indeed, the special significance of a true work of art resides
in the fact that it has escaped from the limitations of the personal and
has soared beyond the personal concerns of its creator.
I must confess from my own experience that it is not
at all easy for a doctor to lay aside his professional bias when considering
a work of art and look at it with a mind cleared of the current biological
causality. But I have come to learn that although a psychology with a purely
biological orientation can explain a good deal about man in general, it
cannot be applied to a work of art and still less to man as creator. A purely
causalistic psychology is only able to reduce every human individual to
a member of the species Homo sapiens, since its range is limited
to what is transmitted by heredity or derived from other sources. But a
work of art is not transmitted or derived - it is a creative reorganization
of those very conditions to which a causalistic psychology must always reduce
it. The plant is not a mere product of the soil; it is a living, self-contained
process which in essence has nothing to do with the character of the soil.
In the same way, the meaning and individual quality of a work of art inhere
within it and not in its extrinsic determinants. One might almost describe
it as a living being that uses man only as a nutrient medium, employing
his capacities according to its own laws and shaping itself to the fulfilment
of its own creative purpose.
But here I am anticipating somewhat, for
I have in mind a particular type of art which I still have to introduce.
Not every work of art originates in the way I have just described. There
are literary works, prose as well as poetry, that spring wholly from the
author's intention to produce a particular result. He submits his material
to a definite treatment with a definite aim in view; he adds to it and subtracts
from it, emphasizing one effect, toning down another, laying on a touch
of colour here, another there, all the time carefully considering the over-all
result and paying strict attention to the laws of form and style. He exercises
the keenest judgment and chooses his words with complete freedom. His material
is entirely subordinated to his artistic purpose; he wants to express this
and nothing else. He is wholly at one with the creative process, no matter
whether be has deliberately made himself its spearhead, as it were, or whether
it has made him its instrument so completely that he has lost all consciousness
of this fact. In either case, the artist is so identified with his work
that his intentions and his faculties are indistinguishable from the act
of creation itself. There is no need, I think, to give examples of this
from the history of literature or from the testimony of the artists themselves.
Nor need I cite examples of the other class
of works which flow more or less complete and perfect from the author's
pen. They come as it were fully arrayed into the world, as Pallas Athene
sprang from the head of Zeus. These works positively force themselves upon
the author; his hand is seized, his pen writes things that his mind contemplates
with amazement. The I work brings with it its own form; anything he wants
to add is rejected, and what he himself would like to reject is thrust back
at him. While his conscious mind stands amazed and empty before this phenomenon,
he is overwhelmed by a flood of thoughts and images which he never intended
to create and which his own will could never have brought into being. Yet
in spite of himself he is forced to admit that it is his own self speaking,
his own inner nature revealing itself and uttering things which he could
never have entrusted to his tongue. He can only obey the apparently alien
impulse within him and follow where it leads, sensing that his work is greater
than himself, and wields a power which is not his and which he cannot command.
Here the artist is not identical with the process of creation; he is aware
that he subordinate to his work or stands outside it, as though he were
- a second person; or as though a person other than himself had fallen within
the magic circle of an alien will.
So when we discuss the psychology of art, we must
bear in mind these two entirely different modes of creation, for much that
is of the greatest importance in judging a work of art depends on this distinction.
It is one that had been sensed earlier by Schiller, who as we know attempted
to classify it in his concept of the sentimental and the naive.
The psychologist would call "sentimental" art introverted and the
"naive" kind extraverted. The introverted attitude is characterized
by the subject's assertion of his conscious intentions and aims against
the demands of the object, whereas the extraverted attitude is characterized
by the subject's subordination to the demands which the object makes upon
him. In my view, Schiller's plays and most of his poems give one a good
idea of the introverted atti-tude: the material is mastered by the conscious
intentions of the poet. The extraverted attitude is illustrated by the second
part of Faust: here the material is distinguished by its refractoriness.
A still more striking example is Nietzsche's Zarathustra, where the
author himself observed how ''one became two.''
From what I have said, it will be apparent that a shift
of psychological standpoint has taken place as soon as one speaks not of
the poet as a person but of the creative process that moves him. When the
focus of interest shifts to the latter, the poet comes into the picture
only as a reacting subject. This is immediately evident in our second category
of works, where the consciousness of he poet is not identical with the creative
process. But in works of the first category the opposite appears to hold
true. Here the poet appears to be the creative process itself, and to create
of his own free will without the slightest feeling of compulsion. He may
even be fully convinced of his freedom of action and refuse to admit that
his work could be anything else than the expression of his will and ability.
Here we are faced with a question which we cannot answer
from the testimony of the poets themselves. It is really a scientific problem
that psychology atone can solve. As I hinted earlier, it might well be that
the poet, while apparently creating out of himself and producing what he
consciously intends, is nevertheless so carried away by the creative impulse
that he is no longer aware of an "alien" will, just as the other type of
poet is no longer aware of his own will speaking to him in the apparently
"alien" inspiration, although this is manifestly the voice of his own self.
The poet's conviction that he is creating in absolute freedom would then
be an illusion: he fancies he is swimming, but in reality an unseen current
sweeps him along.
This is not by any means an academic question, but is
supported by the evidence of analytical psychology. Researches have shown
that there are all sorts of ways in which the conscious mind is not only
influenced by the unconscious but actually guided by it. Yet is there any
evidence for the supposition that a poet, despite his self-awareness, may
be taken captive by his work? The proof may be of two kinds, direct or indirect.
Direct proof would be afforded by a poet who thinks he knows what he is
saying but actually says more than he is aware of. Such cases are not uncommon.
Indirect proof would be found in cases where behind the apparent free will
of the poet there stands a higher imperative that renews its peremptory
demands as soon as the poet voluntarily gives up his creative activity,
or that produces psychic complications whenever his work has to be broken
off against his will.
Analysis of artists consistently shows not only the strength
of the. creative impulse arising from the unconscious, but also its capricious
and willfull character. The biographies of great artists make abundantly
clear that the creative urge is of ten so imperious that it battens on their
humanity and yokes everything to the service of the work, even at the cost
of health and ordinary human happiness. The unborn work in the psyche of
the artist is a force of nature that achieves its end either with tyrannical
might or with the subtle cunning of nature herself, quite regardless of
the personal fate of the man who is its vehicle. The creative urge lives
and grows in him like a tree in the earth from which it draws its nourishment.
We would do well, therefore, to think of the creative process as a living
thing implanted in the human psyche. In the language of analytical psychology
this living thing is an autonomous complex. It is a split-off portion
of the psyche, which leads a life of its own outside the hierarchy of consciousness.
Depending on its energy charge, it may appear either as a mere disturbance
of conscious activities or as a supraordinate authority which can harness
the ego to its purpose. Accordingly, the poet who identifies with the creative
process would he one who acquiesces from the start when the unconscious
imperative begins to function. But the other poet, who feels the creative
Force as something alien, is one who for various reasons cannot acquiesce
and is thus caught unawares.
It might be expected that this difference in its origins
would be perceptible in a work of art. For in the one case it is a conscious
product shaped and designed to have the effect intended. But in the other
we are dealing with an event originating in unconscious nature; with something
that achieves its aim without the assistance of human consciousness, and
often defies it by wilfully insisting on its own form and effect. We would
therefore expect that works belonging to the first class would nowhere overstep
the limits of comprehension, that their effect would be bounded by the author's
intention and would not extend beyond it. But with works of the other class
we would have to be prepared for something suprapersonal that transcends
our understanding to the same degree that the author's consciousness was
in abeyance during the process of creation. We would expect a strangeness
of form and content, thoughts that can only be apprehended intuitively,
a language pregnant with meanings, and images that are true symbols because
they are the best possible expressions for something unknown - bridges thrown
out towards an unseen shore.
These criteria are, by and large, corroborated in practice.
Whenever we are confronted with a work that was consciously planned and
with material that was consciously selected, we find that it agrees with
the first class of qualities, and in the other case with the second. The
example we gave of Schiller's plays on the one hand, and Faust II
on the other, or better still Zarathustra, is an illustration of
this. But I would not undertake to place the work of an unknown poet in
either of these categories without first having examined rather closely
his personal relations with his work. It is not enough to know whether the
poet belongs to the introverted or to the extraverted type, since it is
possible for either type to work with an introverted attitude at one time,
and an extraverted attitude at another. This is partic-ularly noticeable
in the difference between Schiller's plays and his philosophical writings,
between Goethe's perfectly formed poems and the obvious struggle with his
material in Faust II, and between Nietzsche's well-turned aphorisms
and the rushing torrent of Zarathutstra. The same poet can adopt
different atti-tudes to his work at different times, and on this depends
the standard we have to apply.
The question, as we now see, is exceedingly complicated,
and the complication grows even worse when we consider the case of the poet
who identifies with the creative process. For should it turn out that the
apparently conscious and purposeful manner of composition is a subjective
illusion of the poet, then his work would possess symbolic qualities that
are outside the range of his consciousness. They would only be more difficult
to detect, because the reader as well would be unable to get beyond the
bounds of the poet's consciousness which are fixed by the spirit of the
time. There is no Archimedean point outside his world by which he could
lift his time-bound consciousness off its hinges and recognize the symbols
hidden in the poet's work. For a symbol is the intimation of a meaning beyond
the level of our present powers of comprehension.
I raise this question only because I do not want my typological
classification to limit the possible significance of works of art which
apparently mean no more than what they say. But we have often found that
a poet who has gone out of fashion is suddenly rediscovered. This happens
when our conscious develop-ment has reached a higher level from which the
poet can tell us something new. It was always present in his work but was
hidden in a symbol and only a renewal of the spirit of the time permits
us to read its meaning. It needed to be looked at with fresher eyes, for
the old ones could see in it only what they were accustomed to see. Experiences
of this kind should make us cautious, as they bear out my earlier argument.
But works that are openly symbolic do not require this subtle approach;
their pregnant language cries out at us that they mean more than they say.
We can put our finger on the symbol at once, even though we may not be able
to unriddle its meaning to our entire satisfaction. A symbol remains a perpetual
challenge to our thoughts and feelings. That probably explains why a symbolic
work is so stimulating, why it grips us so intensely, but also why it seldom
affords us a purely aesthetic enjoyment. A work that is manifestly not symbolic
appeals much more to our aesthetic sensibility because it is complete in
itself and fulfils its purpose.
What then, you may ask, can analytical psychology contribute
to our fundamental problem, which is the mystery of artistic creation? All
that we have said so far has to do only with the psychological phenomenology
of art. Since nobody can penetrate to the heart of nature you will not expect
psychology to do the impossible and offer a valid explanation of the secret
of creativity. Like every other science, psychology has only a modest contribution
to make towards a deeper understanding of the phenomena of life, and is
no nearer than its sister sciences to absolute knowledge.
We have talked so much about the meaning of works of
art that one can hardly suppress a doubt as to whether art really "means"
anything at all. Perhaps art has no "meaning," at least not as we understand
meaning. Perhaps it is like nature, which simply is and "means" nothing
beyond that. Is "meaning" necessarily more than mere interpretation - an
interpretation secreted into something by an intellect hungry for meaning?
Art, it has been said, is beauty, and "a thing of beauty is a joy for ever."
It needs no meaning, for meaning has nothing to do with art. Within the
sphere of art, I must accept the truth of this statement. But when I speak
of the relation of psychology to art we are outside its sphere, and it is
impossible for us not to Speculate. We must interpret, we must find meanings
in things, other-wise we would be quite unable to think about them. We have
to break down life and events, which are self-contained processes, into
meanings images, concepts well knowing that in doing so we are getting further
away from the living mystery. As long as we ourselves are caught up in the
process of creation, we neither see nor understand; indeed we ought not
to understand, for nothing is more injurious to immediate experience than
cognition. But for the purpose of cognitive understanding we must detach
ourselves from the creative process and look at it from the outside; only
then does it become an image that expresses what we are bound to call "meaning."
What was a mere phenomenon before becomes something that in association
with other phenomena has meaning, that has a definite role to play, serves
certain ends, and exerts meaningful effects. And when we have seen all this
we get the feeling of having understood and explained something. In this
way we meet the demands of science.
When, a little earlier, we spoke of a work
of art as a tree growing out of the nourishing soil, we might equally well
have compared it to a child growing in the womb But as all comparisons are
lame, let us stick to the more precise terminology of Science. You will
remember that I described the nascent work in the psyche of the artist as
an autonomous complex. By this we mean a psychic formation that remains
subliminal until its energy-charge is sufficient to carry it over the threshold
into consciousness. Its association with consciousness does not mean that
it is assimilated, only that it is perceived; but it is not subject to conscious
control, and can be neither inhibited nor voluntarily reproduced. Therein
lies the autonomy of the complex: it appears and disappears in accordance
with its own inherent tendencies, independently of the conscious will. The
creative complex shares this peculiarity with every other autonomous complex.
In this respect it offers an analogy with pathological processes, since
these too are characterized by the presence of autonomous complexes, particularly
in the case of mental disturbances. The divine frenzy of the artist comes
perilously close to a pathological state, though the two things are not
identical. The tertium comparationis is the autonomous complex. But
the presence of autonomous complexes is not in itself pathological, since
normal people, too, fall temporarily or permanently under their domination.
This fact is simply one of the normal peculiarities of the psyche, and for
a man to be unaware of the exist-ence of an autonomous complex merely betrays
a high degree of unconsciousness. Every typical attitude that is to some
extent differentiated shows a tendency to become an autonomous complex and
in most cases it actually does. Again, every instinct has more or less the
character of an autonomous complex. In itself, therefore, in autonomous
complex has nothing morbid about it; only when its manifestations are frequent
and disturbing is it a symptom of illness.
How does an autonomous complex arise? For
reasons which we cannot go into here, a hitherto unconscious portion of
the psyche is thrown into activity, and gains ground by activating the adjacent
areas of association. The energy needed for this is naturally drawn from
consciousness - unless the latter happens to identify with the complex.
But where this does not occur, the drain of energy produces what Janet calls
an abaissement du niveau mental. The intensity of conscious interests
and activities gradually diminishes, leading either to apathy - a condition
very common with artists - or to a regressive development of the conscious
functions, that is, they revert to an infantile and archaic level and undergo
something Tike a degeneration. The "inferior parts of the functions." as
Janet calls them, push to the fore; the instinctual side of the personality
prevails over the ethical, the infantile over the mature, and the unadapted
over the adapted. This too is something we see in the lives of many artists.
The autonomous complex thus develops by using the energy that has been withdrawn
from the conscious control of the personality.
But in what does an autonomous creative complex consist?
Of this we can know next to nothing so long as the artist's work affords
us no insight into its foundations. The work presents us with a finished
picture, and this picture is amenable to analysis only to the extent that
we can recognize it as a symbol. But if we are usually to discover any symbolic
value in it, we have merely established that, so far as we are concerned,
it means no more than what it says, or to put it another way, that it is
no more than what it seems to be. I use the word "seems" because
our own bias may prevent a deeper appreciation of it. At any rate we can
find no incentive and no starting-point for an analysis. But in the case
of a symbolic work we should remember the dictum of Gerhard Hauptmann: "Poetry
evokes out of words the resonance of the primordial word." The question
we should ask, therefore, is: "What primordial image lies behind the imagery
of art?"
This question needs a little elucidation. I am assuming
that the work of art we propose to analyse, as well as being symbolic, has
its source not in the personal unconscious of the poet, but in a
sphere of unconscious mythology whose primordial images are the common heritage
of mankind. I have called this sphere the collective unconscious,
to distinguish it from the personal unconscious. The latter I regard as
the sum total of all those psychic processes and contents which are capable
of becoming Conscious and often do, but are then suppressed because of their
incompatibility and kept subliminal. Art receives tributaries from this
sphere too, but muddy ones; and their predominance, far from making a work
of art a symbol, merely turns it into a symptom. We can leave this kind
of art without injury and without regret to the purgative methods employed
by Freud.
In contrast to the personal unconscious, which
is a relatively thin layer immediately below the threshold of consciousness,
the collective unconscious shows no tendency to become conscious under normal
conditions, nor can it be brought back to recollection by any analytical
technique1, since it was never repressed or forgotten. The collective
unconscious is not to be thought of as a self-subsistent entity; it is no
more than a potentiality handed down to us from primordial times in the
specific form of mnemonic images2 or inherited in the anatomical
structure of the brain. There are no inborn ideas, but there are inborn
possi-bilities of ideas that set bounds to even the boldest fantasy and
keep our fantasy activity within certain categories: a priori ideas, as
it were, the existence of which cannot be ascertained except from their
effects. They appear only in the shaped material of art as the regulative
principles that shape it; that is to say, only by inferences drawn from
the finished work can we reconstruct the age-old original of the primordial
image.
The primordial image, or archetype, is a figure be it
a daemen, a human being, or a process - that constantly recurs in the course
of history and appears wherever creative fantasy is freely expressed. Essentially,
therefore, it is a mythological figure. When we examine these images more
closely, we find that they give form to countless typical experiences of
our ancestors. They are, so to speak the psychic residua of innumerable
experiences of the same type. They present a picture of psychic life in
the average, divided up and projected into the manifold figures of the mythological
pantheon. But the mythological figures are themselves products of creative
fantasy and still have to be translated into conceptual language. Only the
beginnings of such a language exist, but once the necessary concepts are
created they could give us an abstract, scientific understanding of the
unconscious processes that lie at the roots of the primordial images. In
each of these images there is a little piece of human psychology and human
fate, a remnant of the joys and sorrows that have been repeated countless
times in our ancestral history, and on the average follow ever the same
course. It is like a deeply graven river-bed in the psyche, in which the
waters of life, instead of flowing along as before in a broad but shallow
stream, suddenly swell into a mighty river. This happens whenever that particular
set of circumstances is encountered which over long periods of time has
helped to lay down the primordial image.
The moment when this mythological situation reappears
is always characterized by a peculiar emotional intensity; it is as though
chords in us were struck that had never resounded before, or as though forces
whose existence we never suspected were unloosed. What makes the struggle
for adaptation so labo-rious is the fact that we have constantly to be dealing
with indi-vidual and atypical situations. So it is not surprising that when
an archetypal situation occurs we suddenly feel an extraordinary sense of
release, as though transported, or caught up by an overwhelming power. At
such moments we are no longer individ-ual, but the race; the voice of all
mankind resounds in us. The individual man cannot use his powers to the
full unless he is aided by one of those collective representations we call
ideals, which releases all the hidden forces of instinct that are inacces-sible
to his conscious will. The most effective ideals are always fairly obvious
variants of an archetype, as is evident from the fact that they lend themselves
to allegory. The ideal of the "mother country," for instance, is an obvious
allegory of the mother, as is the "fatherland" of the father. Its power
to stir us does not derive from the allegory, but from the symbolical value
of our native land. The archetype here is the participation mys-tique of
primitive man with the soil on which he dwells, and which contains the spirits
of his ancestors.
The impact of an archetype, whether it takes the form
of immediate experience or is expressed through the spoken word, stirs us
because it summons up a voice that is stronger than our own. Whoever speaks
in primordial images speaks with a thousand voices; he enthrals and overpowers,
while at the same time he lifts the idea he is seeking to express out of
the occasional and the transitory into the realm of the ever-enduring. He
transmutes our personal destiny into the destiny of mankind, and evokes
in us all those beneficent forces that ever and anon have enabled humanity
to find a refuge from every peril and to outlive the longest night.
That is the secret of great art, and of its
effect upon us. The creative process, so far as we are able to follow it
at all, consists in the unconscious activation of an archetypal image, and
in elaborating and shaping this image into the finished work. By giving
it shape, the artist translates it into the language of the present, and
so makes it possible for us to find our way back to the deepest springs
of life. Therein lies the social significance of art: it is constantly at
work educating the spirit of the age, conjuring up the forms in which the
age is most lacking. The unsatisfied yearning of the artist reaches back
to the primordial image in the unconscious which is best fitted to compensate
the inadequacy and one-sidedness of the present. The artist seizes on this
image, and in raising it from deepest unconsciousness he brings it into
relation with conscious values, thereby transforming it until it can be
accepted by the minds of his contemporaries according to their powers.
Peoples and times, like individuals, have their
own characteristic tendencies and attitudes. The very word "attitude" betrays
the necessary bias that every marked tendency entails. Direction implies
exclusion, and exclusion means that very many psychic elements that could
play their part in life are denied the right to exist because they are incompatible
with the general attitude. The normal man can follow the general trend without
injury to himself; but the man who takes to the back streets and alleys
because he cannot endure the broad highway will be the first to discover
the psychic elements that are waiting to play their part in the life of
the collective. Here the artist's relative lack of adaptation turns out
to his advantage; it enables him to follow his own yearnings far from the
beaten path, and to discover what it is that would meet the unconscious
needs of his age. Thus, just as the onesidedness of the individuals conscious
attitude is corrected by reactions from the unconscious, so art represents
a process of self-regulation in the life of nations and epochs.
I am aware that in this lecture I have only been able
to sketch out my views in the barest outline. But I hope that what I have
been obliged to omit, that is to say their practical application to poetic
works of art, has been furnished by your own thoughts, thus giving flesh
and blood to my abstract intellectual frame.
|